Georgetown University Slavoj iek Against Human Rights Questions Discussion
Georgetown University Slavoj iek Against Human Rights Questions Discussion Georgetown University Slavoj iek Against Human Rights Questions Discussion ORDER NOW FOR CUSTOMIZED AND ORIGINAL NURSING PAPERS Unformatted Attachment Preview slavoj iek AGAINST HUMAN RIGHTS C ontemporary appeals to human rights within our liberalcapitalist societies generally rest upon three assumptions. First, that such appeals function in opposition to modes of fundamentalism that would naturalize or essentialize contingent, historically conditioned traits. Second, that the two most basic rights are freedom of choice, and the right to dedicate ones life to the pursuit of pleasure (rather than to sacri?ce it for some higher ideological cause). And third, that an appeal to human rights may form the basis for a defence against the excess of power. Let us begin with fundamentalism. Here, the evil (to paraphrase Hegel) often dwells in the gaze that perceives it. Take the Balkans during the 1990s, the site of widespread human-rights violations. At what point did the Balkansa geographical region of South-Eastern Europebecome Balkan, with all that designates for the European ideological imaginary today? The answer is: the mid-19th century, just as the Balkans were being fully exposed to the effects of European modernization. The gap between earlier Western European perceptions and the modern image is striking. Already in the 16th century the French naturalist Pierre Belon could note that the Turks force no one to live like a Turk. Small surprise, then, that so many Jews found asylum and religious freedom in Turkey and other Muslim countries after Ferdinand and Isabella had expelled them from Spain in 1492with the result that, in a supreme twist of irony, Western travellers were disturbed by the public presence of Jews in big Turkish cities. Here, from a long series of examples, is a report from N. Bisani, an Italian who visited Istanbul in 1788: A stranger, who has beheld the intolerance of London and Paris, must be much surprised to see a church here between a mosque and a synagogue, and a dervish by the side of a Capuchin friar. I know not how this government can have admitted into its bosom religions so opposite to its own. It new left review 34 july aug 2005 115 116 nlr 34 must be from degeneracy of Mahommedanism, that this happy contrast can be produced. What is still more astonishing is to ?nd that this spirit of toleration is generally prevalent among the people; for here you see Turks, Jews, Catholics, Armenians, Greeks and Protestants conversing together on subjects of business or pleasure with as much harmony and goodwill as if they were of the same country and religion.1 The very feature that the West today celebrates as the sign of its cultural superioritythe spirit and practice of multicultural toleranceis thus dismissed as an effect of Islamic degeneracy. Georgetown University Slavoj iek Against Human Rights Questions Discussion The strange fate of the Trappist monks of Etoile Marie is equally telling. Expelled from France by the Napoleonic regime, they settled in Germany, but were driven out in 1868. Since no other Christian state would take them, they asked the Sultans permission to buy land near Banja Luka, in the Serb part of todays Bosnia, where they lived happily ever afteruntil they got caught in the Balkan con?icts between Christians. Where, then, did the fundamentalist featuresreligious intolerance, ethnic violence, ?xation upon historical traumawhich the West now associates with the Balkan, originate? Clearly, from the West itself. In a neat instance of Hegels re?exive determination, what Western Europeans observe and deplore in the Balkans is what they themselves introduced there; what they combat is their own historical legacy run amok. Let us not forget that the two great ethnic crimes imputed to the Turks in the 20th centurythe Armenian genocide and the persecution of the Kurdswere not committed by traditionalist Muslim political forces, but by the military modernizers who sought to cut Turkey loose from its old-world ballast and turn it into a European nation-state. Mladen Dolars old quip, based on a detailed reading of Freuds references to the region, that the European unconscious is structured like the Balkans, is thus literally true: in the guise of the Otherness of Balkan, Europe takes cognizance of the stranger in itself, of its own repressed. But we might also examine the ways in which the fundamentalist essentialization of contingent traits is itself a feature of liberal-capitalist democracy. It is fashionable to complain that private life is threatened or even disappearing, in face of the medias ability to expose ones most Quoted in Bozidar Jezernik, Wild Europe: The Balkans in the Gaze of Western Travellers, London 2004, p. 233. 1 iek: Human Rights 117 intimate personal details to the public. True, on condition that we turn things around: what is effectively disappearing here is public life itself, the public sphere proper, in which one operates as a symbolic agent who cannot be reduced to a private individual, to a bundle of personal attributes, desires, traumas and idiosyncrasies. The risk society commonplace according to which the contemporary individual experiences himself as thoroughly denaturalized, regarding even his most natural traits, from ethnic identity to sexual preference, as being chosen, historically contingent, learnedis thus profoundly deceiving. What we are witnessing today is the opposite process: an unprecedented re-naturalization. All big public issues are now translated into attitudes towards the regulation of natural or personal idiosyncrasies. This explains why, at a more general level, pseudo-naturalized ethnoreligious con?icts are the form of struggle which best suits global capitalism. In the age of post-politics, when politics proper is progressively replaced by expert social administration, the sole remaining legitimate sources of con?ict are cultural (religious) or natural (ethnic) tensions. And evaluation is precisely the regulation of social promotion that ?ts with this re-naturalization. Perhaps the time has come to reassert, as the truth of evaluation, the perverted logic to which Marx refers ironically in his description of commodity fetishism, quoting Dogberrys advice to Seacoal at the end of Capitals Chapter 1: To be a well-favoured man is the gift of fortune; but to write and read comes by nature. To be a computer expert or a successful manager is a gift of nature today, but lovely lips or eyes are a fact of culture. Unfreedom of choice As to freedom of choice: I have written elsewhere of the pseudo-choice offered to the adolescents of Amish communities who, after the strictest of upbringings, are invited at the age of seventeen to plunge themselves into every excess of contemporary capitalist culturea whirl of fast cars, wild sex, drugs, drink and so forth.2 After a couple of years, they are allowed to choose whether they want to return to the Amish way. Since they have been brought up in virtual ignorance of American society, the youngsters are quite unprepared to cope with such permissiveness, which in most cases generates a backlash of unbearable anxiety. The 2 The constitution is dead. Long live proper politics, Guardian, 4 June 2005. 118 nlr 34 vast majority vote to return to the seclusion of their communities. This is a perfect case of the dif?culties that invariably accompany freedom of choice: while Amish children are formally given a free choice, the conditions in which they must make it render the choice unfree. The problem of pseudo-choice also demonstrates the limitations of the standard liberal attitude towards Muslim women who wear the veil: acceptable if it is their own free choice rather than imposed on them by husbands or family. However, the moment a woman dons the veil as the result of personal choice, its meaning changes completely: it is no longer a sign of belonging to the Muslim community, but an expression of idiosyncratic individuality. In other words, a choice is always a meta-choice, a choice of the modality of the choice itself: it is only the woman who does not choose to wear a veil that effectively chooses a choice. This is why, in our secular liberal democracies, people who maintain a substantial religious allegiance are in a subordinate position: their faith is tolerated as their own personal choice, but the moment they present it publicly as what it is for thema matter of substantial belongingthey stand accused of fundamentalism. Georgetown University Slavoj iek Against Human Rights Questions Discussion Plainly, the subject of free choice, in the tolerant, multicultural sense, can only emerge as the result of an extremely violent process of being uprooted from ones particular life-world. The material force of the ideological notion of free choice within capitalist democracy was well illustrated by the fate of the Clinton Administrations ultra-modest health reform programme. The medical lobby (twice as strong as the infamous defence lobby) succeeded in imposing on the public the idea that universal healthcare would somehow threaten freedom of choice in that domain. Against this conviction, all enumeration of hard facts proved ineffective. We are here at the very nerve-centre of liberal ideology: freedom of choice, grounded in the notion of the psychological subject, endowed with propensities which he or she strives to realize. And this especially holds today, in the era of a risk society in which the ruling ideology endeavours to sell us the very insecurities caused by the dismantling of the welfare state as the opportunity for new freedoms. If labour ?exibilization means you have to change jobs every year, why not see it as a liberation from the constraints of a permanent career, a chance to reinvent yourself and realize the hidden potential of your personality? If there is a shortfall on your standard health insurance and retirement plan, meaning you have to iek: Human Rights 119 opt for extra coverage, why not perceive it as an additional opportunity to choose: either a better lifestyle now or long-term security? Should this predicament cause you anxiety, the second modernity ideologist will diagnose you as desiring to escape from freedom, of an immature sticking to old stable forms. Even better, when this is inscribed into the ideology of the subject as the psychological individual, pregnant with natural abilities, you will automatically tend to interpret all these changes as the outcome of your personality, not as the result of being thrown around by market forces. Politics of jouissance What of the basic right to the pursuit of pleasure? Todays politics is ever more concerned with ways of soliciting or controlling jouissance. The opposition between the liberal-tolerant West and fundamentalist Islam is most often condensed as that between, on the one side, a womans right to free sexuality, including the freedom to display or expose herself and to provoke or disturb men; and, on the other side, desperate male attempts to suppress or control this threat. (The Taliban forbade metaltipped heels for women, as the tapping sounds coming from beneath an all-concealing burka might have an overpowering erotic appeal.) Both sides, of course, mystify their position ideologically and morally. For the West, womens right to expose themselves provocatively to male desire is legitimized as their right to enjoy their bodies as they please. For Islam, the control of female sexuality is legitimized as the defence of womens dignity against their being reduced to objects of male exploitation. So when the French state prohibits Muslim girls from wearing the veil in school, one can claim that they are thus enabled to dispose of their bodies as they wish. But one can also argue that the true traumatic point for critics of Muslim fundamentalism was that there were women who did not participate in the game of making their bodies available for sexual seduction, or for the social exchange and circulation involved in this. In one way or another, all the other issuesgay marriage and adoption, abortion, divorcerelate to this. What the two poles share is a strict disciplinary approach, differently directed: fundamentalists regulate female self-presentation to forestall sexual provocation; pc feminist liberals impose a no-less-severe regulation of behaviour aimed at containing forms of harassment. 120 nlr 34 Liberal attitudes towards the other are characterized both by respect for otherness, openness to it, and an obsessive fear of harassment. In short, the other is welcomed insofar as its presence is not intrusive, insofar as it is not really the other. Georgetown University Slavoj iek Against Human Rights Questions Discussion Tolerance thus coincides with its opposite. My duty to be tolerant towards the other effectively means that I should not get too close to him or her, not intrude into his spacein short, that I should respect his intolerance towards my over-proximity. This is increasingly emerging as the central human right of advanced capitalist society: the right not to be harassed, that is, to be kept at a safe distance from others. The same goes for the emergent logic of humanitarian or paci?st militarism. War is acceptable insofar as it seeks to bring about peace, or democracy, or the conditions for distributing humanitarian aid. And does the same not hold even more for democracy and human rights themselves? Human rights are ok if they are rethought to include torture and a permanent emergency state. Democracy is ok if it is cleansed of its populist excesses and limited to those mature enough to practise it. Caught in the vicious cycle of the imperative of jouissance, the temptation is to opt for what appears its natural opposite, the violent renunciation of jouissance. This is perhaps the underlying motif of all so-called fundamentalismsthe endeavour to contain (what they perceive as) the excessive narcissistic hedonism of contemporary secular culture with a call to reintroduce the spirit of sacri?ce. A psychoanalytic perspective immediately enables us to see why such an endeavour goes wrong. The very gesture of casting away enjoymentEnough of decadent selfindulgence! Renounce and purify!produces a surplus-enjoyment of its own. Do not all totalitarian universes which demand of their subjects a violent (self-)sacri?ce to the cause exude the bad smell of a fascination with a lethal-obscene jouissance? Conversely, a life oriented towards the pursuit of pleasure will entail the harsh discipline of a healthy lifestylejogging, dieting, mental relaxationif it is to be enjoyed to the maximum. The superego injunction to enjoy oneself is immanently intertwined with the logic of sacri?ce. The two form a vicious cycle, each extreme supporting the other. The choice is never simply between doing ones duty or striving for pleasure and satisfaction. This elementary choice is always redoubled by a further one, between elevating ones striving for pleasure into ones supreme duty, and doing ones duty not for dutys sake but for the grati?cation it brings. In the ?rst case, pleasures are my duty, and the pathological striving for pleasure is located in the iek: Human Rights 121 formal space of duty. In the second case, duty is my pleasure, and doing my duty is located in the formal space of pathological satisfactions. Defence against power? But if human rights as opposition to fundamentalism and as pursuit of happiness lead us into intractable contradictions, are they not after all a defence against the excess of power? Marx formulated the strange logic of power as in excess by its very nature in his analyses of 1848. In The Eighteenth Brumaire and The Class Struggles in France, he complicated in a properly dialectical way the logic of social representation (political agents representing economic classes and forces).Georgetown University Slavoj iek Against Human Rights Questions Discussion In doing so, he went much further than the usual notion of these complications, according to which political representation never directly mirrors social structurea single political agent can represent different social groups, for instance; or a class can renounce its direct representation and leave to another the job of securing the politico-juridical conditions of its rule, as the English capitalist class did by leaving to the aristocracy the exercise of political power. Marxs analyses pointed towards what Lacan would articulate, more than a century later, as the logic of the signi?er. Apropos the Party of Order, formed after the defeat of the June insurrection, Marx wrote that only after Louis-Napoleons December 10 election victory allowed it to cast off its coterie of bourgeois republicans was the secret of its existence, the coalition of Orléanists and Legitimists into one party, disclosed. The bourgeois class fell apart into two big factions which alternatelythe big landed proprietors under the restored monarchy and the ?nance aristocracy and the industrial bourgeoisie under the July Monarchyhad maintained a monopoly of power. Bourbon was the royal name for the predominant in?uence of the interests of the one faction, Orléans the royal name for the predominant in?uence of the interests of the other factionthe nameless realm of the republic was the only one in which both factions could maintain with equal power the common class interest without giving up their mutual rivalry.3 This, then, is the ?rst complication. When we are dealing with two or more socio-economic groups, their common interest can only be represented in the guise of the negation of their shared premise: the common denominator of the two royalist factions is not royalism, but 3 Marx and Engels, Selected Works, vol. i, Moscow 1969, p. 83. 122 nlr 34 republicanism. (Just as today, the only political agent that consistently represents the interests of capital as such, in its universality, above particular factions, is the social liberal Third Way.) Then, in The Eighteenth Brumaire, Marx dissected the makeup of the Society of December 10, Louis-Napoleons private army of thugs: Alongside decayed roués with dubious means of subsistence and of dubious origin, alongside ruined and adventurous offshoots of the bourgeoisie, were vagabonds, discharged soldiers, discharged jailbirds, escaped galley slaves, swindlers, mountebanks, lazzaroni, pickpockets, tricksters, gamblers, maquereaux [pimps], brothel-keepers, porters, literati, organ-grinders, rag-pickers, knife-grinders, tinkers, beggarsin short, the whole inde?nite, disintegrated mass, thrown hither and thither, which the French call la bohème; from this kindred element Bonaparte formed the core of the Society of December 10 . . . This Bonaparte, who constitutes himself chief of the lumpen proletariat, who here alone rediscovers in mass form the interests which he personally pursues, who recognizes in this scum, offal, refuse of all classes the only class upon which he can base himself unconditionally, is the real Bonaparte, the Bonaparte sans phrases.4 The logic of the Party of Order is here brought to its radical conclusion. In the same way that the only common denominator of all royalist factions is republicanism, the only common denominator of all classes is the excremental excess, the refuse, the remainder, of all classes. That is to say, insofar as the leader perceives himself as standing above class interests, his immediate class base can only be the excremental remainder of all classes, the rejected non-class of each class. And, as Marx develops in another passage, it is this support from the social abject which enables Bonaparte to shift his position as required, representing in turn each class against the others. As the executive authority which has made itself independent, Bonaparte feels it to be his task to safeguard bourgeois orde Purchase answer to see full attachment Get a 10 % discount on an order above $ 100 Use the following coupon code : NURSING10
With us, you are either satisfied 100% or you get your money back-No monkey business